Philosophy 355 Contemporary Moral Problems Darwall Winte
r 1996
ABORTION I
I. Moral vs. legal questions
A. Under some circumstance or other, is abortion
morally permissible vs. should it be permitted legally?
B. It is possible to think the answer to the second
question is positive even in cases where it is not morally
permissible.
II. The moral question also is different from the question
who should choose. One way to think of the moral issue is
to ask what sorts of considerations are relevant to the
question a woman (a couple?) faces when they ask, "should I
(ethically) have an abortion?"
III. The legal situation.
A. Roe v. Wade still governs.
i. 'Person' in its constitutional sense does not
apply to the fetus at any stage.
ii. Three trimesters:
a. first--abortion left to the judgment of
the woman's physician; no state
regulation
b. second--state may regulate in interest of
the woman's heath
c. after viability the state may regulate or
even proscribe in light of its interest in
potential life.
B. Subsequent restrictions: waiting period, informed
consent, consent of one parent if the individual is 16 years
of age or less.
IV. Plan of Discussion
A. Abortion I--The Moral Status of the Fetus
B. Abortion II--What Does the Right to Life Entail?
C. Abortion III--Abortion and Gender Justice
V. What kind of question is, "Is the Fetus a Person?"
A. Different from "To What Species Does the Fetus
Belong?"
B. Different from "Is the Fetus Alive?"
C. In the relevant sense, questions like: "When Does
Life Begin?", etc. are not biological but irreducibly moral
questions.
D. To make it explict, we might ask: "What is the
moral standing or status of the fetus?" "What moral claim
does the fetus make on us?"
E. In particular, at what stage, if any, does the
fetus have the same status or dignity that a person does
when we think of morality as binding us as a community of
equal moral persons? Or, at what point, if any, does the
fetus have the same right to life that we think of all
persons as having?
F. Note: If the fetus is not a person in the relevant
sense, at some stage, it does not follow that it does not
make a serious moral claim of some sort on us, just not the
same sort of claim that a person does.
VI. Mary Anne Warren agues that the fetus is a person at no
stage of development.
A. Warren argues that to be a person is to have
"enough" of the following cluster of features.
1. consciousness and the capacity to feel pain;
2. reasoning (the developed capacity to solve new
and relatively complex problems)
3. self-motivated activity
4. capacity to communicate messages of an
indefinite variety of types, etc.
5. self-awareness
Since the fetus has relatively few of these
features, it is not a person.
B. What lies behind this list? Here is a line of
thought that leads to the conclusion that self-awareness is
particularly important to the right to life.
1. Suppose you think that human beings have a
kind of right to life that other animals do not have. Why
would this be?
2. Perhaps it is because human beings have an
interest in their lives as extended wholes. We are
concerned not just with the quality of the moments of our
lives (e.g., whether they are pleasurable or painful), but
also with what our lives amount to as a whole.
3. Only a being with self-consciusness could have
this concern.
4. Therefore, a capacity for self-consciousness
might be thought to lie behind the right to life we think
person's have. [Question: does this same interest ground a
right to determine when our lives will end, insofar as this
is possible?]
C. Problem with this position: What about newborns?
Will they not lack the right to life on these grounds also?
D. Warren agrees, but argues that it does not follow
that it would not be wrong to kill a newborn. Consider her
response and ask whether it might not apply to the fetus
also.
VI. John Noonan argues that we should resist the discourse
of rights.
A. Rights vs. family membership. A better question
than when does the fetus have the right to life is when is
the fetus appropriately included in the "famly of man."
B. How to be interpreted? Not by intellectual
argument. Rather by a form of perception that only an
emotional encounter makes possible. Compare being convinced
by an argument that, say, discrimination against gays is
wrong vs. seeing that it is wrong by a vivid depiction of
the pain in suffering it causes, say in a film.
C. If the question is not one of rights, but of what
would be the caring thing, or of how we should care for the
fetus, then this may be impossible to setting without an
emotionally honest and open encounter.
D. Noonan argues that when we do so encounter the
fetus (by looking at it, or interacting with its movements)
we find that we cannot help but care about it in a way that
reveals its importance, something whose life matters in a
way that it would be seriously wrong to kill it for any
other purpose but to save the life of the mother.
VII. These positions are at the two extermes.
A. Warren: the fetus is at no stage a person.
B. Noonan: the fetus is at every stage a person.
There are also various moderate positions.
C. While at no stage does the fetus have a right to
life, it is nonetheless deserving of serious concern at any
stage past X, and abortion is wrong after that stage.
D. The fetus has the right to life at stage X and
beyond.