4.4 History

Twelve scatterplots showing which percentage of the articles in each journal in each year are in the category history of philosophy. A brief summary of the data follows. In an average year in Mind, 8.9% of the articles are in the category history of philosophy. History of philosophy is most prevalent in Mind in 1925 when it accounts for 26.4% of the articles in the journal. And it is least prevalent in 1999 when it accounts for 1.0% of the articles in the journal. In an average year in Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 7.2% of the articles are in the category history of philosophy. History of philosophy is most prevalent in Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society in 1943 when it accounts for 19.0% of the articles in the journal. And it is least prevalent in 1960 when it accounts for 1.5% of the articles in the journal. In an average year in Ethics, 7.8% of the articles are in the category history of philosophy. History of philosophy is most prevalent in Ethics in 1951 when it accounts for 19.3% of the articles in the journal. And it is least prevalent in 2001 when it accounts for 1.3% of the articles in the journal. In an average year in Philosophical Review, 13.4% of the articles are in the category history of philosophy. History of philosophy is most prevalent in Philosophical Review in 1930 when it accounts for 27.6% of the articles in the journal. And it is least prevalent in 2012 when it accounts for 1.4% of the articles in the journal. In an average year in Analysis, 2.3% of the articles are in the category history of philosophy. History of philosophy is most prevalent in Analysis in 1947 when it accounts for 5.5% of the articles in the journal. And it is least prevalent in 1933 when it accounts for 0.2% of the articles in the journal. In an average year in Philosophy and Public Affairs, 3.1% of the articles are in the category history of philosophy. History of philosophy is most prevalent in Philosophy and Public Affairs in 1982 when it accounts for 6.6% of the articles in the journal. And it is least prevalent in 1981 when it accounts for 1.0% of the articles in the journal. In an average year in Journal of Philosophy, 7.9% of the articles are in the category history of philosophy. History of philosophy is most prevalent in Journal of Philosophy in 1939 when it accounts for 18.7% of the articles in the journal. And it is least prevalent in 1988 when it accounts for 1.7% of the articles in the journal. In an average year in Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 13.8% of the articles are in the category history of philosophy. History of philosophy is most prevalent in Philosophy and Phenomenological Research in 1941 when it accounts for 34.9% of the articles in the journal. And it is least prevalent in 2010 when it accounts for 4.0% of the articles in the journal. In an average year in Philosophy of Science, 3.2% of the articles are in the category history of philosophy. History of philosophy is most prevalent in Philosophy of Science in 1953 when it accounts for 8.7% of the articles in the journal. And it is least prevalent in 1979 when it accounts for 0.6% of the articles in the journal. In an average year in Noûs, 4.8% of the articles are in the category history of philosophy. History of philosophy is most prevalent in Noûs in 1990 when it accounts for 17.1% of the articles in the journal. And it is least prevalent in 2002 when it accounts for 0.9% of the articles in the journal. In an average year in The Philosophical Quarterly, 9.3% of the articles are in the category history of philosophy. History of philosophy is most prevalent in The Philosophical Quarterly in 1950 when it accounts for 35.6% of the articles in the journal. And it is least prevalent in 1999 when it accounts for 1.7% of the articles in the journal. In an average year in British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 3.1% of the articles are in the category history of philosophy. History of philosophy is most prevalent in British Journal for the Philosophy of Science in 1953 when it accounts for 11.0% of the articles in the journal. And it is least prevalent in 1995 when it accounts for 0.6% of the articles in the journal.

Figure 4.10: Proportion of each journal’s yearly publications in history of philosophy.

None of these lines seem to be trending up, and several of them are trending down. But there are differences in the ways that they are trending.

  • Ethics is a slow, steady decline.
  • Journal of Philosophy is a very rapid decline over the 1960s, between a high equilibrium before that, and a much lower equilibrium after.
  • Mind falls off a cliff around World War II, around the same time Ryle takes over.
  • Philosophy and Phenomenological Research falls away around 1990, as they stop taking quite as seriously the part of their name that says “phenomenological”. (I don’t know how closely this tracks with Ernest Sosa becoming editor of PPR.)

So part of what’s going on is what I mentioned in the previous section. Specialist journals are focusing more on their specialty, and this means doing less of everything else. And in part this feels like the long influence of Gilbert Ryle. This might seem odd given that Ryle published in history of philosophy, including several papers on early modern and on phenomenology, but there is some independent evidence of this. This is from an article his successor as Mind editor, D. M. Hamlyn, wrote about Ryle’s editorship.

[Ryle] said, for example, that, except for Greek Philosophy, he tended to not accept papers on the history of philosophy, and he also said something about what was normally the desirable maximum length for papers. I must say that I found what he had to say on the first point rather odd, though he was absolutely right on the second. (Hamlyn 2003, 5–12)

Whatever Hamlyn thought, it doesn’t seem to have affected the publications much. You can’t see his ascension (in 1971) in the data here. And I think this decision of Ryle’s (or of the board of Mind at the time Ryle was appointed) had a large impact on the role of journal articles in history of philosophy. (Though note Hamlyn says in that paper that Ryle left him a backlog of 2 years’ material to publish. So any break would be 1973 not 1971. Both these facts, that Mind was only publishing its backlog in 1972 and 1973, and that they were still papers accepted by Ryle, are quite interesting in the context of the differences in citation rates between Mind and its US counterparts in those years. But that’s a story for another study.)

8 scatterplots showing which percentage of the articles in all journals in each year from 1900 onwards are in the each of the topics category history of philosophy. A brief summary of the data follows. In an average year, 1.6% of the articles are in the Dewey and pragmatismtopic. Dewey and pragmatism is most prevalent in 1908 when it accounts for 5.1% of the articles in all journals. In an average year, 0.8% of the articles are in the Heidegger and Husserltopic. Heidegger and Husserl is most prevalent in 1941 when it accounts for 4.5% of the articles in all journals. In an average year, 0.5% of the articles are in the Humetopic. Hume is most prevalent in 1905 when it accounts for 1.5% of the articles in all journals. In an average year, 0.8% of the articles are in the Kanttopic. Kant is most prevalent in 1908 when it accounts for 2.6% of the articles in all journals. In an average year, 1.1% of the articles are in the ancienttopic. Ancient is most prevalent in 1909 when it accounts for 4.2% of the articles in all journals. In an average year, 1.1% of the articles are in the early moderntopic. Early modern is most prevalent in 1930 when it accounts for 4.5% of the articles in all journals. In an average year, 2.4% of the articles are in the other historytopic. Other history is most prevalent in 1916 when it accounts for 7.3% of the articles in all journals. In an average year, 0.6% of the articles are in the social contract theorytopic. Social contract theory is most prevalent in 1926 when it accounts for 1.5% of the articles in all journals.

Figure 4.11: Topics in history of philosophy.

Table 4.1: Points excluded from topic graph for history of philosophy
Subject Year Frequency
Other history 1916 0.0729
Other history 1928 0.0698

Two things jump out here.

One is that when history of philosophy was a major part of the journals, it was driven by the weird mix from other history, not the big names. Remember that the paradigm article from Topic 4 was about James Marsh.

The other is that Dewey and pragmatism is also a big part of the story, at least when history is prominent in the journals.

But note that both of these things suggest that to some extent the strength of history before World War II is a touch overstated. Other History includes a bunch of papers that are, if history, very much the first draft of history. For example, for several decades Philosophical Review published an annual piece on philosophy in France, usually written by André Lalande. (A bunch of these papers can be accessed via PhilPapers, but I haven’t looked at many of them personally.) It’s kind of history—it surveys what has happened in a place in a historical period. It’s just that the period was, you know, the year that just passed. So not really that historical. All of these articles are classed as history by the algorithm. That doesn’t explain what happened with Mind, of course, but there is stuff there that is only history for want of somewhere else to put it.

And while many of the pragmatism papers are genuinely history papers—they are about works by Dewey several decades after those works were written—some of them are simply works of pragmatist philosophy. (And of course Dewey is still alive, and even publishing, into the 1940s. I think it’s possible to do historical work on a figure while they are still alive, but it’s a bit odd.)

So I don’t think we should think there was really a golden age for publishing history of philosophy in these journals that has now ceased. They did publish things that were historical. And papers on Marsh or on Geulincx are really a kind of history that we just don’t see in the current journals. Maybe we need to bring back that kind of history of philosophy. (As I’ll discuss at the end of the book, there is some evidence that we are bringing that kind of history back.)